The problem of personal identity

The problem of personal identityExams are only weeks away. Perhaps many of you woke up earlier than usual this morning so that, after the usual chores, you could continue revising a subject that you began working on last night. I did. But as is often the case in philosophy, this very ordinary scenario raises some fascinating and remarkably difficult questions. One of them is called ‘the problem of personal identity’, which we could put, at a first pass, like this: How do you know that the ‘you’ who awoke this morning and continued revising is one and the same person as the ‘you’ who was revising and then went to sleep last night? Let’s call this the Basic Question.

I realize that this problem – or even the suggestion that it actually is a problem — may sound ridiculous to many of you. But I shall try, as Bouwsma said a philosopher must, to ‘quicken the sense of the queer’ – that is, to explain why it is in fact so wonderfully problematic. And later, I shall try to explain some of the practical implications that follow from how we ultimately answer questions like the Basic Question.

Let’s call the ‘you’ who was revising last evening ‘the evening person.’ And let’s call the ‘you’ who awoke this morning ‘the morning person’. Now the obvious answer to the Basic Question – the answer most of us would be first inclined to give – is this: I know that the morning person is one and the same person as the evening person because they have one and the same body. That’s not to say, of course, that each body is composed of precisely the same stuff, for e.g. we know that the evening person’s body lost some atoms as it covered up and moved about in bed last night. Rather, it’s to say that the morning and evening persons are one and the same organism, viz. the same human being. And an organism can remain the same despite alterations in its physical constitution as long as it’s continuously alive.

This is undoubtedly a reasonable response. But consider the following scenario. Your alarm goes off in the morning, and as you silence it, you begin to think both about your morning chores, and about the topic you’ll soon be revising. You move about your home with complete familiarity, feeding your cat, preparing your lunch, smiling at the sight of your favorite family portrait, and so on. You then sit at your desk, turn on your computer and enter the appropriate password. As always, the first thing you do is check your email. You open the first message and see it contains a video, which you (unwisely) choose to watch. As it begins, you see that it’s footage from last night of yourself asleep in your bed. But then you see a team of what appear to be scientists enter your bedroom, and you watch as your sleeping body is removed from your bed, its skull is opened, and its brain removed. Another body is then brought into the room, its skull is opened, and its brain is removed. The brains are then switched, so that your body receives the other brain, and the other body receives your brain. Finally, this other body, which now contains your brain, is placed back in your bed. As you continue to watch the video, you see this unfamiliar body awake and turn off the alarm, after which it leaves the room. The video then ends. Now the very next thing you do, of course, is rush to the nearest mirror. Sure enough, you discover that the reflected body is not your own, but the unfamiliar body you first saw in the video you just finished watching.

Philosophers call this sort of imaginary scenario a thought experiment. You might think of thought experiments as roughly analogous to scientific experiments. In a scientific experiment, you isolate physical variables in order to test them in a variety of ways. But in a thought experiment, what you isolate are conceptual variables. And you test them by examining them for logical coherence, and by noting, and then clarifying and analyzing, the intuitive responses they elicit as you reflect upon them.

So what would you say about the thought experiment we just considered? Would that morning person – whom we shall call ‘the other-body person’ — be one and the same person as you, i.e. as the evening person? Most of us would be inclined to say that he is. For we can imagine scenarios in which friends and family encounter the other-body person and become persuaded that it’s ‘really’ you because of the detailed knowledge he has of your past. Or we can suppose that you come to learn that the person who was previously associated with the body you now seem to possess spoke French, was illiterate and aggressive. The other-body person, however, is not like this at all, but is rather like the evening person in all these respects: he speaks English, is relatively meek, and, since he claims to be a University of London student, is highly literate. That is, most of us would conclude that what the video recorded is best described as our getting a different body (that is the other-body person who awoke in the morning is the evening person), and not as our getting a different brain (that is, the other-body person who awoke in the morning is not the evening person, but the aggressive, illiterate French speaking person with a new set of memories, dispositions and abilities).

So we may now be inclined to answer the Basic Question as follows: The morning person and the evening person are one and the same person because they share one and the same brain. But suppose we tweak the brain-switch thought experiment in the following way. The team of scientists on the video don’t remove any part of your brain, but rather hook you up to a machine that extracts all the information your brain contains. Then, having done the same thing to the other person, they use the machine to ‘insert’ the information extracted from his brain into your brain, and vice versa. Then, they place his body and brain, which now contains your brain’s information, into your bed. Would you still be inclined to say that the other-body person who awakes is one and the same person as the evening person?

Note that every consideration that led you to conclude that the other-body person was one and the same person as the evening person obtains in this case as well. The person who awakes speaks English, not French; he’s relatively meek, not aggressive; and he’s not illiterate, but rather has the abilities we’d expect of a University of London student. Further, he has intimate knowledge of the evening person’s life. And we can say that there are facts about the other-body person who awakes in the morning that depend on facts about the evening person, e.g. ‘the other-body person knows the evening body person’s exam subjects so well because the evening body person had worked so hard revising them’. That is, it seems as if what inclined us in the first thought experiment to say that the other-body person was one and the same person as the evening person was not continuity of the brain itself, which we never referenced in adducing the reasons that led us to conclude that the other-body person was identical with the evening person. For if memory and personality resided with some other organ, such as the heart, we’d have been no more compelled to conclude that a brain transplant would result in a body swap than we are now to conclude that heart transplants result in body swaps. That is, it seems that what really mattered in the first thought experiment was psychological continuity, and not any kind of bodily continuity.

But notice that now we’ve completely transformed our answer to the Basic Question! For the response that at first seemed so obvious – viz. that the morning person was one and the same person as the evening person because they shared one and the same body – now seems all but impotent. But what about the new criterion we’ve hit upon, viz. psychological continuity – can we depend upon it to answer the Basic Question?

Let’s tweak the thought experiment one more time. Now, as in the second thought experiment, the scientists merely extract information from your brain. But during the reinsertion process, the machine malfunctions. This goes unnoticed by the scientists, however, who proceed as they did in the previous thought experiment. Now suppose that the other-body person awakes as before, with the memories, personality and dispositions of the evening person. And suppose that, after watching the video, he goes through the same process of reasoning we previously outlined, and concludes that he is the evening person. So far, so good. But now suppose that unknown to the other-body person, your original body awakes somewhere else, and due to the machine’s malfunctioning, it too possesses your memories, personality and dispositions! That is, during the extraction and reinsertion process, the evening person’s brain information was ‘inserted’ into both brains!

Most of us would now be inclined to say that the person who awakes with the evening person’s memories and personality and his body and brain is the evening person. But then what about the other-body person? None of the reasons that led us to conclude that he is the evening person have changed. Rather, all that’s changed is that we now have a competitor to identity with the evening person – a competitor who seems to have a stronger claim to identity with the evening person only because he is both psychologically and physically continuous with the evening person.

But this raises (at least) two new questions. First, if physical continuity was of no consequence in the first two thought experiments, why should it be of any consequence now? And second, should this result affect how we view the first two thought experiments? For in the second thought experiment, it seemed clear that the other-body person was identical with the evening person; yet how can that result be contingent on something like whether the information extracting machine malfunctions? Note that even the first thought experiment is not immune to this problem. For suppose that the brain of the other person was dropped and irreparably damaged during the removal process, and so your brain was divided in half. One half of your brain was placed in the other person’s skull, while one half remained in your skull. Yet again we’d have two people who are psychologically continuous with the evening person, and this time both are at least partly physically continuous with him as well. And the physical continuity involved is precisely the sort we judged to be most important in the second thought experiment, viz. continuity of brain. So now, if we’re inclined to say that the person with the evening person’s body is identical with the evening person, it seems as if it’s continuity of the rest of the body, and not of the brain or of any psychological properties, that leads us to that result. Yet that’s the very first condition we rejected! Hence, as is so often the case in philosophy, what at first appeared to be no problem at all has now, on careful reflection, left us utterly confused!

But so what? Does anything of practical significance turn on how we answer these sorts of questions? Let’s consider just one of a host of contentious issues that are deeply affected by how we answer questions about personal identity, viz. the issue of abortion. Note that in our discussion above, we regularly distinguished persons from the bodies of persons, or persons from organisms. Are these distinctions tenable? If not – that is, if a person just is his body – then you are plausibly one and the same person as the fetus that was in your mother’s womb. And then, if we want to say that you have certain rights now, and that you have them simply in virtue of being a person, it’s going to be difficult to deny that the fetus, who is identical with you, had those rights as well. But if these distinctions are tenable, then you and that fetus may not be one and the same person – indeed, the fetus may not be a person at all. And this will affect what rights we’re willing to ascribe to it, or whether we choose to ascribe it any rights whatsoever.

We have, of course, barely scratched the surface of the problem of personal identity, and of the practical considerations that are affected by how we attempt to resolve it. But I hope this much is clear: what at first appeared to be a non-issue has, on careful philosophical reflection, turned out to be not only completely baffling, but of critical importance as well! Yet notice that our resulting confusion is what we might call an informed confusion – that is, we in our confused state understand the issue much better than those who believe they have easy answers to the questions it raises. And properly understanding an issue is surely a reasonable precondition to ultimately answering the questions it raises.

Eric is studying for the BA Philosophy by distance learning in Rhode Island, USA.

2 thoughts on “The problem of personal identity

  1. beautiful, this article should be given to people who are new to philosophical thinking, and dont know much about how it works. Upon the issue of personal identity, I shall say that all of the thought experiments implicitly assume, in the first place, that such and such can plausibly happen in the real world to being with. So, for example, what if the moment scientists try to mess with the brain of the person in bed(either try to securely remove it or just to extract memory and thoughts etc) , he dies immediately? Further on, consider the situation whereby although these scientists are successful in extracting the information from the brain of the person in bed(or his brain itself), but the moment they put it in the brain (or skull) of the other person and then connect it to the body, both people die? (since we havent carried anything out of such sort in the real world, as far as i am aware, so what would happen, on our part, remains in the realm of speculation)I mean, what if its inherently impossible for these experiments to come to some fruition in the real world?

    Suppose for the sake of argument that they actually are, physically unrealizable. so would any conclusions obtained from such a thought experiment mean anything for us?

  2. Hi Mohammed, thanks for the kind words and for the excellent question!

    Let me first say that your question, if generalized, gets at some very deep issues concerning the relation between philosophy and science that I don’t currently have any firm or settled judgments about. I’m very much a philosophical novice, so still I have a wonderfully rich world of ideas and arguments to work my way through!

    That caveat aside, I’ll try to say something about the point you raised.

    Let’s suppose, as you do, that it turns out that body swaps, of any kind, are physically impossible for human beings. I suppose my first thought is that, to fully work out the implications of this fact on how we ought to think about personal identity, we’d have to know why they’re ultimately impossible. For if they turn out to be impossible in some ways, the facts prohibiting body swaps could conceivably point to the existence of a ‘further fact’ about persons, say the existence of a soul or psychological substance. But if they turn out to be impossible in other ways, the facts prohibiting body swaps could conceivably point to an identification of the human person with the brain, or the human body/organism (when alive and functioning in a particular way). And if they turn out to be impossible in still other ways, the facts prohibiting body swaps could conceivably point to an inconsistency in our very concept of a person itself.

    We can further distinguish the ways in which body swaps may be said to be impossible. So suppose they’re only impossible for human beings, due to e.g. some physical laws governing the functioning of biological substances. We could still, it seems to me, ask if our concepts ‘human being/human person’ and ‘person’ could come apart, so that ‘human persons’ form a subset of all possible persons. That is, we could ask if we can conceive of non-human persons. So, suppose we take a Lockean view of persons as self aware, rational beings. We might then conceive of non-biological persons, such as robots, or even of alien persons whose biology is sufficiently different from ours. That is, even if the specific scenarios I adduced on the post above turn out to be physically impossible for human beings/human persons, we can ask ourselves if there are other ways in which persons may exist — ways that would permit body swaps. And reflecting on those scenarios would help us to think more clearly about our concept of a person as such, of which human persons would just be one specific type.

    We could also ask, as scientists often do, what would happen if we tweaked the physical laws governing the prohibition on body swaps among human persons in the actual world. That is, can we conceive of a world in which human beings exist who are not governed by these laws? If so, then we can say that while body swaps between human persons are physically impossible, they’re nonetheless logically possible. And reflections on logical possibility can deepen our understanding of what a person ultimately is, and hence of what a human person ultimately is.

    So my short answer is 1. the implications of the physical impossibility of body swaps on our notions of persons and personal identity will largely turn on the details of why body swaps are physically impossible, 2. even if body swaps are physically impossible for human beings, we can reflect on body swap scenarios involving non-human persons to see of they deepen our understanding of personhood as such, and 3. we could ask if body swapping between human persons is merely physically impossible, or if it’s logically possible as well; and we could conclude that if it’s the former only, then reflecting on body swap scenarios between human persons may still provide us with insight into the nature of human persons.

Leave a comment

Fill in your details below or click an icon to log in:

WordPress.com Logo

You are commenting using your WordPress.com account. Log Out / Change )

Twitter picture

You are commenting using your Twitter account. Log Out / Change )

Facebook photo

You are commenting using your Facebook account. Log Out / Change )

Google+ photo

You are commenting using your Google+ account. Log Out / Change )

Connecting to %s